ROB KOONS
  • Home
  • Published articles
  • Work in Progress
  • Lectures
  • Contact and Links
  • Old Blog (2021-22)

The Rigorous Thomist

A Blog by Rob Koons

The Kalam Argument, part 1

8/29/2021

0 Comments

 
The Kalam argument for God’s existence, which was pioneered by John Philoponus (490-570), developed by Islamic philosophers such as al-Kindi and al-Ghazali, and championed in recent years by William Lane Craig (Craig 1979) and by me (Koons 2014), is an attempt to prove that the universe must have had a cause, a role which God seems best suited to fit. The argument typically takes the following form:
 
1. Whatever begins to exist must have a cause.
2. The universe began to exist, because time itself is bounded in the past.
Therefore, the universe had a cause.
 
The first premise has a great deal of intuitive appeal, and there are severe epistemological costs to countenancing the idea of uncaused origins. For instance, the skeptical scenario popularized by Bertrand Russell—How do we know that the universe didn’t simply appear 5 minutes ago?—would be a live possibility in the absence of an a priori causal principle similar to premise 1. So, let’s focus on premise 2.

The typical Kalam strategy for defending premise 2 is to argue that time past is not eternal, that is, that there is some finite temporal bound to all past events. Now, it is not immediately obvious that a finite bound to the past entails that the “universe” began to exist. First, it is not obvious that there is such a thing as the universe: perhaps the plurality of things that exist at a time t do not compose a single whole at t. We might try to avoid this composition question by modifying premise 2 into 2.1:
 
2.1 There is a time t such that everything existing at t began to exist at t, and nothing existed at any time prior to t.
 
In order to get the desired conclusion, we would also have to modify premise 1 as follows:
 
1.1 If some things xx began to exist at time t, then there must be some thing y or things yy not among the xx such that y (or the yy) caused the xx to begin to exist at t. (I am using double letters as plural variables, following George Boolos’s plural quantification (Boolos 1984). One should read ‘yy’ as ‘the y’s (plural)’.)
 
We will also have to rule out the possibility that the things coming into existence at the first moment of time might have been caused by things existing at later times:
 
3. If the yy cause the xx to exist at t, then the yy exist at t or at some time earlier than t or eternally.

Form 1.1, 2.1, and 3, we can reach the conclusion that something that exists eternally caused the beginning-to-exist of all the things that existed at the first moment of time (if there is such a first moment).
 
There is, however, a further lacuna to fill: from the fact that the past is finite in extent or duration, it does not follow that there is a first moment of time. For example, it could be that no event occurs 14 billion or more years ago, but for every length of time L years less than 14 billion years, there are events that occurred exactly L years ago. That is, there might be a finite bound on the past, with past moments that approach arbitrarily close to that boundary, but no moment that reaches it, i.e., no absolutely first moment. (Think of the set of positive real numbers, which approach arbitrarily close to zero without actually including it.)

Instead of looking for proof of the finitude of the past, we should look instead for support of what Alexander Pruss (2016) has called causal finitism. If we can show that every event has a finite causal history (i.e., no causal loops and no causal infinite regresses), then we can infer that there are uncaused events. If we can further assume that everything that begins to exist at a time must have a cause and that every non-eternal or fully temporal thing must have begun to exist at some time (because the past is finite), then we can conclude that all uncaused things must be eternal in nature (i.e., existing “outside” or “beyond” time itself). At that point, we might be able to show that such an eternal cause of temporal events must be relevantly godlike.
 
Here is a version of this Pruss-inspired argument:
 
P1. Every event has a finite causal history (no causal loops or infinite regresses).
P2. For everything that begins to exist (at some point in time), the event of its beginning to exist must have a cause.
P3. Every non-eternal thing began to exist at some point in time (since the past of each non-eternal thing is finite in length).
P4. If the yy cause the xx to begin to exist at t, then the yy exist at t or at some time earlier than t or eternally. [Premise 3 above]
Therefore, every non-eternal thing is ultimately caused to exist by some eternal (godlike) thing.

This proof assumes (in premise 3) that, for anything that begins to exist, there is a first moment of its existence. That seems pretty reasonable. In addition, one could probably derive this from causal finitism. Suppose, for contradiction, that some x has a finite past but no first moment of existence. Then it seems that there must an infinite regress of periods of x's existence, each caused by its predecessor, in contradiction to the principle of causal finitism.

But suppose one doesn't buy either of these moves. Then there would have to be a single initial period P of x's existence, a period which lacks a first instant. In that case, premises P2 and P4 (suitably modified) would entail that there must be some cause of x's beginning to exist, a cause that is either timeless or active at a time t that is prior to and adjacent to period P. And so the proof will go through.

The proof is pretty simple. Suppose x is some non-eternal thing. By P2 it begins to exist, and by P3 its beginning to exist must have a cause. By P4, this cause must either exist eternally or at the same or earlier time than that of the beginning of x's existence. If the cause is an eternal being, we're done. If the cause is a non-eternal being, then it must have a beginning of its existence. Premise P1 rules out an infinite regress of temporal causes. So, there must be an eternal cause.
0 Comments



Leave a Reply.

    Author

    Rob Koons, a professor of philosophy, trained in the analytic tradition at Oxford and UCLA. Specializing in the further development of the Aristotle-Aquinas tradition in metaphysics and the philosophy of nature.

    Archives

    August 2022
    June 2022
    May 2022
    February 2022
    January 2022
    September 2021
    August 2021
    July 2021
    June 2021

    Categories

    All
    Acts Of Existence
    Actualism
    Actuality
    Agency
    Being
    Causal Finitism
    Causation
    Change
    Classical Theism
    Contingency
    Design
    Divine Freedom
    Divine Simplicity
    Efficient Causation
    Essence
    Eternity
    Ethics
    Evil
    Existence
    Fifth Way
    First Cause
    First Mover
    First Way
    Five Ways
    Fourth Way
    Free Will
    God's Existence
    Goodness
    Grace
    Grim Reaper
    Haecceity
    Immateriality
    Infinite Regress
    Infinity
    Instrumental Causation
    Intelligence
    Joe Schmid
    Justice
    Kalam Argument
    Knowledge
    Love
    Matter
    Maximum Being
    Metaethics
    Modal Collapse
    Modality
    Motion
    Necessary Being
    Parts/Wholes
    Passions
    Passive Potentiality
    Patchwork Principle
    Perfection
    Persistence
    Platonism
    Potentiality
    Powers
    Predestination
    Prime Matter
    Providence
    Pure Actuality
    Real Distinction
    Relativity
    Scotism
    Second Way
    Sin
    Substantial Change
    Teleology
    Third Way
    Time
    Unity Of God
    Virtue
    Will Of God

    RSS Feed

Site powered by Weebly. Managed by Bluehost
  • Home
  • Published articles
  • Work in Progress
  • Lectures
  • Contact and Links
  • Old Blog (2021-22)